友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
the critique of judgement-第60部分
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!
nt of taste is in fact a disguised judgement of reason on the perfection discovered in a thing and the reference of the manifold in it to an end; and that it is consequently only called aesthetic on account of the confusion that here besets our reflection; although fundamentally it is teleological。 In this latter case the solution of the antinomy with the assistance of transcendental ideas might be declared otiose and nugatory; and the above laws of taste thus reconciled with the objects of sense; not as mere phenomena; but even as things…in…themselves。 How unsatisfactory both of those alternatives alike are as a means of escape has been shown in several places in our exposition of judgements of taste。 If; however; our deduction is at least credited with having been worked out on correct lines; even though it may not have been sufficiently clear in all its details; three ideas then stand out in evidence。 Firstly; there is the supersensible in general; without further determination; as substrate of nature; secondly; this same supersensible as principle of the subjective finality of nature for our cognitive faculties; thirdly; the same supersensible again; as principle of the ends of freedom; and principle of the common accord of these ends with freedom in the moral sphere。
SS 58。 The idealism of the finality alike of nature and of art; as the unique principle of the aesthetic judgement。
The principle of taste may; to begin with; be placed on either of two footings。 For taste may be said invariably to judge on empirical grounds of determination and such; therefore; as are only given a posteriori through sense; or else it may be allowed to judge on an a priori ground。 The former would be the empiricism of the critique of taste; the latter its rationalism。 The first would obliterate the distinction that marks off the object of our delight from the agreeable; the second; supposing the judgement rested upon determinate concepts; would obliterate its distinction from the good。 In this way beauty would have its locus standi in the world completely denied; and nothing but the dignity of a separate name; betokening; maybe; a certain blend of both the above…named kinds of delight; would be left in its stead。 But we have shown the existence of grounds of delight which are a priori; and which therefore; can consist with the principle of rationalism; and which are yet incapable of being grasped by definite concepts。 As against the above; we may say that the rationalism of the principle of taste may take the form either of the realism of finality or of its idealism。 Now; as a judgement of taste is not a cognitive judgement; and as beauty is not a property of the object considered in its own account; the rationalism of the principle of taste can never be placed in the fact that the finality in this judgement is regarded in thought as objective。 In other words; the judgement is not directed theoretically; nor; therefore; logically; either (no matter if only in a confused estimate); to the perfection of the object; but only aesthetically to the harmonizing of its representation in the imagination with the essential principles of judgement generally in the subject。 For this reason the judgement of taste; and the distinction between its realism and its idealism; can only; even on the principle of rationalism; depend upon its subjective finality interpreted in one or other of two ways。 Either such subjective finality is; in the first case; a harmony with our judgement pursued as an actual (intentional) end of nature (or of art); or else; in the second case; it is only a supervening final harmony with the needs of our faculty of judgement in its relation to nature and the forms which nature produces in accordance with particular laws; and one that is independent of an end; spontaneous and contingent。 The beautiful forms displayed in the organic world all plead eloquently on the side of the realism of the aesthetic finality of nature in support of the plausible assumption that beneath the production of the beautiful there must lie a preconceived idea in the producing cause…that is to say an end acting in the interest of our imagination。 Flowers; blossoms; even the shapes of plants as a whole; the elegance of animal formations of all kinds; unnecessary for the discharge of any function on their part; but chosen as it were with an eye to our taste; and; beyond all else; the variety and harmony in the array of colours (in the pheasant; in crustacea; in insects; down even to the meanest flowers); so pleasing and charming to the eyes; but which; inasmuch as they touch the bare surf ace; and do not even here in any way all act the structure; of these creatures…a matter which might have a necessary bearing on their internal ends…seem to be planned entirely with a view to outward appearance: all these lend great weight to the mode of explanation which assumes actual ends of nature in favour of our aesthetic judgement。 On the other hand; not alone does reason; with its maxims enjoining upon us in all cases to avoid; as far as possible; any unnecessary multiplication of principles; set itself against this assumption; but we have nature in its free formations displaying on all sides extensive mechanical proclivity to producing forms seemingly made; as it were; for the aesthetic employment of our judgement; without affording the least support to the supposition of a need for anything over and above its mechanism; as mere nature; to enable them to be final for our judgement apart from their being grounded upon any idea。 The above expression; 〃free formations〃 of nature; is; however; here used to denote such as are originally set up in a fluid at rest where the volatilization or separation of some constituent (sometimes merely of caloric) leaves the residue on solidification to assume a definite shape or structure (figure or texture) which differs with specific differences of the matter; but for the same matter is invariable。 Here; however; it is taken for granted that; as the true meaning of a fluid requires; the matter in the fluid is completely dissolved and not a mere admixture of solid particles simply held there in suspension。 The formation; then; takes place by a concursion; i。e。; by a sudden solidification… not by a gradual transition from the fluid to the solid state; but; as it were; by a leap。 This transition is termed crystallization。 Freezing water offers the most familiar instance of a formation of this kind。 There the process begins by straight threads of ice forming。 These unite at angles of 60〃; whilst others similarly attach themselves to them at every point until the whole has turned into ice。 But while this is going on; the water between the threads of ice does not keep getting gradually more viscous; but remains as thoroughly fluid as it would be at a much higher temperature; although it is perfectly ice…cold。 The matter that frees itself that makes its sudden escape at the moment of solidification…is a considerable quantum of caloric。 As this was merely required to preserve fluidity; its disappearance leaves the existing ice not a whit colder than the water which but a moment before was there as
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!