友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
the critique of judgement-第15部分
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!
; like all empirical rules; general only; not universal; the latter being what the judgement of taste upon the beautiful deals or claims to deal in。 It is a judgement in respect of sociability so far as resting on empirical rules。 In respect of the good; it is true that judgements also rightly assert a claim to validity for every one; but the good is only represented as an object of universal delight by means of a concept; which is the case neither with the agreeable nor the beautiful。
SS 8。 In a judgement of taste the universality of delight is only represented as subjective。
This particular form of the universality of an aesthetic judgement; which is to be met in a judgement of taste; is a significant feature; not for the logician certainly; but for the transcendental philosopher。 It calls for no small effort on his part to discover its origin; but in return it brings to light a property of our cognitive faculty which; without this analysis; would have remained unknown。 First; one must get firmly into one's mind that by the judgement of taste (upon the beautiful) the delight in an object is imputed to every one; yet without being founded on a concept (for then it would be the good); and that this claim to universality is such an essential factor of a judgement by which we describe anything as beautiful; that were it not for its being present to the mind it would never enter into any one's head to use this expression; but everything that pleased without a concept would be ranked as agreeable。 For in respect of the agreeable; every one is allowed to have his own opinion; and no one insists upon others agreeing with his judgement of taste; which is what is invariably done in the judgement of taste about beauty。 The first of these I may call the taste of sense; the second; the taste of reflection: the first laying down judgements merely private; the second; on the other hand; judgements ostensibly of general validity (public); but both alike being aesthetic (not practical) judgements about an object merely in respect of the bearings of its representation on the feeling of pleasure or displeasure。 Now it does seem strange that while with the taste of sense it is not alone experience that shows that its judgement (of pleasure or displeasure in something) is not universally valid; but every one willingly refrains from imputing this agreement to others (despite the frequent actual prevalence of a considerable consensus of general opinion even in these judgements); the taste of reflection; which; as experience teaches; has often enough to put up with a rude dismissal of its claims to universal validity of its judgement (upon the beautiful); can (as it actually does) find it possible for all that to formulate judgements capable of demanding this agreement in its universality。 Such agreement it does in fact require from every one for each of its judgements of taste the persons who pass these judgements not quarreling over the possibility of such a claim; but only failing in particular cases to come to terms as to the correct application of this faculty。 First of all we have here to note that a universality which does not rest upon concepts of the object (even though these are only empirical) is in no way logical; but aesthetic; i。 e。; does not involve any objective quantity of the judgement; but only one that is subjective。 For this universality I use the expression general validity; which denotes the validity of the reference of a representation; not to the cognitive faculties; but to the feeling of pleasure or displeasure for every subject。 (The same expression; however; may also be employed for the logical quantity of the judgement; provided we add objective universal validity; to distinguish it from the merely subjective validity which is always aesthetic。) Now a judgement that has objective universal validity has always got the subjective also; i。e。; if the judgement is valid for everything which is contained under a given concept; it is valid also for all who represent an object by means of this concept。 But from a subjective universal validity; i。 e。; the aesthetic; that does not rest on any concept; no conclusion can be drawn to the logical; because judgements of that kind have no bearing upon the object。 But for this very reason the aesthetic universality attributed to a judgement must also be of a special kind; seeing that it does not join the predicate of beauty to the concept of the object taken in its entire logical sphere; and yet does extend this predicate over the whole sphere of judging subjects。 In their logical quantity; all judgements of taste are singular judgements。 For; since I must present the object immediately to my feeling of pleasure or displeasure; and that; too; without the aid of concepts; such judgements cannot have the quantity of judgements with objective general validity。 Yet by taking the singular representation of the object of the judgement of taste; and by comparison converting it into a concept according to the conditions determining that judgement; we can arrive at a logically universal judgement。 For instance; by a judgement of the taste I describe the rose at which I am looking as beautiful。 The judgement; on the other hand; resulting from the comparison of a number of singular representations: 〃Roses in general are beautiful;〃 is no longer pronounced as a purely aesthetic judgement; but as a logical judgement founded on one that is aesthetic。 Now the judgement; 〃The rose is agreeable〃 (to smell) is also; no doubt; an aesthetic and singular judgement; but then it is not one of taste but of sense。 For it has this point of difference from a judgement of taste; that the latter imports an aesthetic quantity of universality; i。e。; of validity for everyone which is not to be met with in a judgement upon the agreeable。 It is only judgements upon the good which; while also determining the delight in an object; possess logical and not mere aesthetic universality; for it is as involving a cognition of the object that 〃they are valid of it; and on that account valid for everyone。 In forming an estimate of objects merely from concepts; all representation of beauty goes by the board。 There can; therefore; be no rule according to which any one is to be compelled to recognize anything as beautiful。 Whether a dress; a house; or a flower is beautiful is a matter upon which one declines to allow one's judgement to be swayed by any reasons or principles。 We want to get a look at the object with our own eyes; just as if our delight depended on sensation。 And yet; if upon so doing; we call the object beautiful; we believe ourselves to be speaking with a universal voice; and lay claim to the concurrence of everyone; whereas no private sensation would be decisive except for the observer alone and his liking。 Here; now; we may perceive that nothing is postulated in the judgement of taste but such a universal voice in respect of delight that it is not mediated by concepts; consequently; only the possibility of an aesthetic judgement capable of being at the same time deemed valid for everyone。 The judgement of taste itself does not postulate the agreement of everyone (for it is only co
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!