友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
恐怖书库 返回本书目录 加入书签 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 『收藏到我的浏览器』

the critique of judgement-第57部分

快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!


nd thus demands a certain seriousness in its presentation; as taste does in estimating it。

PART1|SEC2            FIRST PART CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT           SECTION II。 DIALECTIC OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT。

                          SS 55。

  For a power of judgement to be dialectical it must first of all be rationalizing; that is to say; its judgements must lay claim to universality;* and do so a priori; for it is in the antithesis of such judgements that dialectic consists。 Hence there is nothing dialectical in the irreconcilability of aesthetic judgements of sense (upon the agreeable and disagreeable)。 And in so far as each person appeals merely to his own private taste; even the conflict of judgements of taste does not form a dialectic of taste…for no one is proposing to make his own judgement into a universal rule。 Hence the only concept left to us of a dialectic affecting taste is one of a dialectic of the critique of taste (not of taste itself) in respect of its principles: for; on the question of the ground of the possibility of judgements of taste in general; mutually conflicting concepts naturally and unavoidably make their appearance。 The transcendental critique of taste will; therefore; only include a part capable of bearing the name of a dialectic of the aesthetic judgement if we find an antinomy of the principles of this faculty which throws doubt upon its conformity to law; and hence also upon its inner possibility。

  *Any judgement which sets up to be universal may be termed a rationalizing judgement (indicium ratiocinans); for so far as universal it may serve as the major premiss of a syllogism。 On the other hand; only a judgement which is thought as the conclusion of a syllogism; and; therefore; as having an a priori foundation; can be called rational (indicium ratiocinatum)。

       SS 56。 Representation of the antinomy of taste。

  The first commonplace of taste is contained in the proposition under cover of which every one devoid of taste thinks to shelter himself from reproach: every one has his own taste。 This is only another way of saying that the determining ground of this judgement is merely subjective (gratification or pain); and that the judgement has no right to the necessary agreement of others。   Its second commonplace; to which even those resort who concede the right of the judgement of taste to pronounce with validity for every one; is: there is no disputing about taste。 This amounts to saying that; even though the determining ground of a judgement of taste be objective; it is not reducible to definite concepts; so that in respect of the judgement itself no decision can be reached by proofs; although it is quite open to us to contend upon the matter; and to contend with right。 For though contention and dispute have this point in common; that they aim at bringing judgements into accordance out of and by means of their mutual opposition; yet they differ in the latter hoping to effect this from definite concepts; as grounds of proof; and; consequently; adopting objective concepts as grounds of the judgement。 But where this is considered impracticable; dispute is regarded as alike out of the question。   Between these two commonplaces an intermediate proposition is readily seen to be missing。 It is one which has certainly not become proverbial; but yet it is at the back of every one's mind。 It is that there may be contention about taste (although not a dispute)。 This proposition; however; involves the contrary of the first one。 For in a manner in which contention is to be allowed; there must be a: hope of coming to terms。 Hence one must be able to reckon on grounds of judgement that possess more than private Validity and are thus not merely subjective。 And yet the above principle (Every one has his own taste) is directly opposed to this。   The principle of taste; therefore; exhibits the following antinomy:   1。 Thesis。 The judgement of taste is not based upon concepts; for; if it were; it would be open to dispute (decision by means of proofs)。   2。 Antithesis。 The judgement of taste is based on concepts; for otherwise; despite diversity of judgement; there could be no room even for contention in the matter (a claim to the necessary agreement of others with this judgement)。

           SS 57。 Solution of the antinomy of taste。

  There is no possibility of removing the conflict of the above principles; which underlie every judgement of taste (and which are only the two peculiarities of the judgement of taste previously set out in the Analytic) except by showing that the concept to which the object is to refer in a judgement of this kind is not taken in the same sense in both maxims of the aesthetic judgement; that this double sense; or point of view; in our estimate; is necessary for our power of transcendental judgement; and that nevertheless the false appearance arising from the confusion of one with the other is a natural illusion; and so unavoidable。   The judgement of taste must have reference to some concept or other; as otherwise it would be absolutely impossible for it to lay claim to necessary validity for every one。 Yet it need not on that account be provable from a concept。 For a concept may be either determinable; or else at once intrinsically undetermined and indeterminable。 A concept of the understanding; which is determinable by means of predicates borrowed from sensible intuition and capable of corresponding to it; is of the first kind。 But of the second kind is the transcendental rational concept of the supersensible; which lies at the basis of all that sensible intuition and is; therefore; incapable of being further determined theoretically。   Now the judgement of taste applies to objects of sense; but not so as to determine a concept of them for the understanding; for it is not a cognitive judgement。 Hence it is a singular representation of intuition referable to the feeling of pleasure; and; as such; only a private judgement。 And to that extent it would be limited in its validity to the individual judging: the object is for me an object of delight; for others it may be otherwise; every one to his taste。   For all that; the judgement of taste contains beyond doubt an enlarged reference on the part of the representation of the object (and at the same time on the part of the subject also); which lays the foundation of an extension of judgements of this kind to necessity for every one。 This must of necessity be founded upon some concept or other; but such a concept as does not admit of being determined by intuition; and affords no knowledge of anything。 Hence; too; it is a concept which does not afford proof of the judgement of taste。 But the mere pure rational concept of the supersensible lying at the basis of the object (and of the judging subject for that matter) as object of sense; and thus as phenomenon; is just such a concept。 For unless such a point of view were adopted there would be no means of saving the claim of the judgement of taste to universal validity。 And if the concept forming the required basis were a concept of understanding; though a mere confused one; as; let us say; of perfection; answering to which the sensible intuition of the beautiful mig
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 1
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!