友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
恐怖书库 返回本书目录 加入书签 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 『收藏到我的浏览器』

the critique of judgement-第58部分

快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!


d one; as; let us say; of perfection; answering to which the sensible intuition of the beautiful might be adduced; then it would be at least intrinsically possible to found the judgement of taste upon proofs; which contradicts the thesis。   All contradiction disappears; however; if I say: The judgement of taste does depend upon a concept (of a general ground of the subjective finality of nature for the power of judgement); but one from which nothing can be cognized in respect of the object; and nothing proved; because it is in itself indeterminable and useless for knowledge。 Yet; by means of this very concept; it acquires at the same time validity for every one (but with each individual; no doubt; as a singular judgement immediately accompanying his intuition): because its determining ground lies; perhaps; in the concept of what may be regarded as the supersensible substrate of humanity。   The solution of an antinomy turns solely on the possibility of two apparently conflicting propositions not being in fact contradictory; but rather being capable of consisting together; although the explanation of the possibility of their concept transcends our faculties of cognition。 That this illusion is also natural and for human reason unavoidable; as well as why it is so; and remains so; although upon the solution of the apparent contradiction it no longer misleads us; may be made intelligible from the above considerations。   For the concept; which the universal validity of a judgement must have for its basis; is taken in the same sense in both the conflicting judgements; yet two opposite predicates are asserted of it。 The thesis should therefore read: The judgement of taste is not based on determinate concepts; but the antithesis: The judgement of taste does rest upon a concept; although an indeterminate one (that; namely; of the supersensible substrate of phenomena); and then there would be no conflict between them。   Beyond removing this conflict between the claims and counter…claims of taste we can do nothing。 To supply a determinate objective principle of taste in accordance with which its judgements might be derived; tested; and proved; is an absolute impossibility; for then it would not be a judgement of taste。 The subjective principle…that is to say; the indeterminate idea of the supersensible within us …can only be indicated as the unique key to the riddle of this faculty; itself concealed from us in its sources; and there is no means of making it any more intelligible。   The antinomy here exhibited and resolved rests upon the proper concept of taste as a merely reflective aesthetic judgement; and the two seemingly conflicting principles are reconciled on the ground that they may both be true; and this is sufficient。 If; on the other hand; owing to the fact that the representation lying at the basis of the judgement of taste is singular; the determining ground of taste is taken; as by some it is; to be agreeableness; or; as others; looking to its universal validity; would have it; the principle of perfection; and if the definition of taste is framed accordingly; the result is an antinomy which is absolutely irresolvable unless we show the falsity of both propositions as contraries (not as simple contradictories)。 This would force the conclusion that the concept upon which each is founded is self…contradictory。 Thus it is evident that the removal of the antinomy of the aesthetic judgement pursues a course similar to that followed by the Critique in the solution of the antinomies of pure theoretical reason; and that the antinomies; both here and in the Critique of Practical Reason; compel us; whether we like it or not; to look beyond the horizon of the sensible; and to seek in the supersensible the point of union of all our faculties a priori: for we are left with no other expedient to bring reason into harmony with itself。

                       REMARK 1。

  We find such frequent occasion in transcendental philosophy for distinguishing ideas from concepts of the understanding that it may be of use to introduce technical terms answering to the distinction between them。 I think that no objection will be raised to my proposing some。 Ideas; in the most comprehensive sense of the word; are representations referred to an object according to a certain principle (subjective or objective); in so far as they can still never become a cognition of it。 They are either referred to an intuition; in accordance with a merely subjective principle of the harmony of the cognitive faculties (imagination and understanding); and are then called aesthetic; or else they are referred to a concept according to an objective principle and yet are incapable of ever furnishing a cognition of the object; and are called rational ideas。 In the latter case; the concept is a transcendent concept; and; as such; differs from a concept of understanding; for which an adequately answering experience may always be supplied; and which; on that account; is called immanent。   An aesthetic idea cannot become a cognition; because it is an intuition (of the imagination) for which an adequate concept can never be found。 A rational idea can never become a cognition; because it involves a concept (of the supersensible); for which a commensurate intuition can never be given。   Now the aesthetic idea might; I think; be called an inexponible representation of the imagination; the rational idea; on the other hand; an indemonstrable concept of reason。 The production of both is presupposed to be not altogether groundless; but rather (following the above explanation of an idea in general) to take place in obedience to certain principles of the cognitive faculties to which they belong (subjective principles in the case of the former and objective in that of the latter)。   Concepts of the understanding must; as such; always be demonstrable (if; as in anatomy; demonstration is understood in the sense merely of presentation)。 In other words; the object answering to such concepts must always be capable of being given an intuition (pure or empirical); for only in this way can they become cognitions。 The concept of magnitude may be given a priori in the intuition of space; e。g。; of the right line; etc。; the concept of cause in impenetrability; in the impact of bodies; etc。 Consequently both may be verified by means of an empirical intuition; i。e。; the thought of them may be indicated (demonstrated; exhibited) in an example; and this it must be possible to do: for otherwise there would be no certainty of the thought not being empty; i。e。; having no object。   In logic the expressions demonstrable or indemonstrable are ordinarily employed only in respect of propositions。 A better designation would be to call the former propositions only mediately; and the latter; propositions immediately; certain。 For pure philosophy; too; has propositions of both these kinds…meaning thereby true propositions which are in the one case capable; and in the other incapable; of proof。 But; in its character of philosophy; while it can; no doubt; prove on a priori grounds; it cannot demonstrate…unless we wish to give the complete go…by to the meaning of the word which makes demonstrate (ostendere; exhibere) equivalent
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 1
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!